Is Critical Naturalism Necessary?
Martine Prange, Ties van Gemert, Willem van der Deijl-Kloeg, Paolo Santori
Krisis 2023, 43 (1): 106-109.
Abstract
The prior issue of Krisis (42:1) published Critical Naturalism: A Manifesto, with the aim to
instigate a debate of the issues raised in this manifesto the necessary re-thinking of the role
(and the concept) of nature in critical theory in relation to questions of ecology, health, and
inequality. Since Krisis considers itself a place for philosophical debates that take contempo-
rary struggles as starting point, it issued an open call and solicited responses to the manifesto.
This is one of the sixteen selected responses, which augment, specify, or question the assump-
tions and arguments of the manifesto.
Keywords
Critical Naturalism Manifesto, Nietzsche, Neoliberalism, Braidotti
DOI
https://doi.org/10.21827/krisis.43.1.40967
Licence
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC
BY 4.0). © 2023 The author(s).
Krisis 2023, 43 (1)
106
Is Critical Naturalism Necessary?
Martine Prange, Ties van Gemert, Willem van der Deijl-Kloeg, Paolo Santori
After a collective reading and discussion of the Critical Manifesto, members of the Tilburg
Research Group Philosophy of Humanity, Culture, and Ethics (PHC&E) and Tilburg Center
for Moral Philosophy, Epistemology and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS) decided to write the
present response, combining each member’s remarks and questions. We believe that the chal-
lenges addressed by the Manifesto are pertinent and urgent. We are sceptical, however, of the
ways in which the authors address the problems and of the version of “critical naturalism” they
propose. The following four points capture some of our reservations:
1. The question is, first, what the authors mean by “critical naturalism,” since “natural-
ism” is hardly defined; and, second, what critical naturalism has to offer or add to ex-
isting theories that have been concerned with similar issues. Think, for instance, of
Braidotti’s critical posthumanism (Braidotti 2013). Think also of Latour’s thought on
the Anthropocene and his concept of “Gaia” as an ethical alternative for “Earth” or
“nature” (Latour 2017); think perhaps even of the Romantic tradition running from
Humboldt to Nietzsche, which is marked by its claim for the unity of humanity and
nature (Nietzsche 1980). The authors of the manifesto overlook these, and other, tradi-
tions, and as a result invite us to reinvent the wheel. They seem to operate from an
awareness that Critical Theory currently offers little to the (philosophical and political)
climate debates, and that any serious social critique needs to. As they claim, the human-
nature relationship needs to be rethought because, they state, the social is embedded in
nature. Naturalism, in this context, seems to mean: “critical theory turning its focus to
nature,” which makes a very meagre concept. How does this concept strengthen or defy
existing concepts from the long traditions of naturalism in both continental and analytic
philosophy? What strikes us as odd in addition to this, is that they advocate a turn to
Hegel the giant thinker of “spirit,” to address nature. Is Hegel really a greater thinker
of nature and the humanity-nature relationship than, say, Humboldt, Nietzsche, or
Latour? In sum, it is praiseworthy that the authors try to open up a way for scholars in
the Frankfurter tradition to rethink the humanity-nature relationship in light of the cur-
rent climate crisis. The question is, however, whether we are not better off with
Krisis 2023, 43 (1)
107
Nietzsche’s attempt at “naturalizing” humanity, Latour’s concept of Gaia, and
Braidotti’s post-critical humanism which fruitfully combines an inter-relational eth-
ics, anti-speciesism, and capitalist critique at least as long as the authors have no clear
definition of “nature” and “naturalism.”
2. Critique is a reflective gesture where thought turns towards itself and scrutinizes the
conditions and validity of its content (Kant 1929 [1787]). Naturalism, by contrast, as-
pires to remain faithful to the appearances and to introduce nothing exterior to the given
(Neurath 1973 [1921]; Quine 1969). How can we combine these two commitments?
This is no hint at a paradox, but an invitation to make this tension productive (Deleuze
and Guattari 1980). Perhaps one could even argue that intensifying this tension is the
very task of any critical naturalism. We wonder how the authors intend to come to
terms with this tension. Will they give up on critique as reflection and simply equate
critique with care? Will they answer by insisting that anyone who asks the question
remains a victim of a false, outdated dichotomy? Or might they be willing to rethink
the relation between reality and appearance (Brassier 2013)?
3. Is a critical naturalistic theory necessary? How can such a theory motivate us to
change? Isn’t it already obvious what needs to be done? We need to significantly cut
our emissions by swiftly shifting alternative energy resources (Broome 2012) and to
stop exploiting animals (Singer 1977; Regan 1983). In short, to take our duty of caring
for the planet seriously. We doubt whether critical naturalism has the theoretical re-
sources to contribute to solving the challenges involved in these practices. How can it
contribute to problems such as whether we should use geo-engineering to fight climate
change (e.g. Mittiga 2019), or whether we should start eating lab-grown meat (e.g.
Schaefer and Savulescu 2014)? If we know what to do but simply miss the motivation
for action, how can critical naturalism aid us in reforming and ameliorating our inter-
ests to live our lives as environmentally, ecologically, and animal-friendly as possible?
4. Can we speak about capitalism in a singular tense, identifying it with neoliberalism, as
the authors of the manifesto seem to do? There are good reasons to avoid this oversim-
plification. First, the geopolitical context shows that such major players as the USA are
not holding on anymore to the neoliberal dogma of the Washington Consensus,
Krisis 2023, 43 (1)
108
favouring protectionism and commercial wars over global liberalization and open fron-
tiers. Second, there is a lot of variety in capitalism. Take, as just one example, the
Italian entrepreneurial fabric. There we find ample family businesses, small-size enter-
prises, cooperatives and so on. It is a “spirit” and practice of capitalism very different
from the Anglo-American, neoliberal one, made of vertical corporations and anony-
mous markets (Bruni and Zamagni 2016). Reducing the plural economic realities to
one dominant standard under the label of “neoliberalism” risks overshadowing poten-
tially good practices. The same goes for economics. While there is a neoliberal main-
stream in research and teaching in business schools and economics faculties, there is a
growing field of economic research which challenges that. To list a few examples, think
of Raworth’s Doughnut Economics (Raworth 2017) as it is applied to cities, or Maz-
zucato’s view of The Entrepreneurial State (Mazzucato 2013), not to mention the Das-
gupta Review (Dasgupta 2021), funded by HM Treasury (curiously enough a neoliberal
institution), that advocates for a new understanding of nature in economics. All of this
calls for a change in the economic curricula, from the neoliberal focus on private goods
and rational interest toward common goods and care. By lumping together economics,
capitalism, and neoliberalism, and considering them simply as the enemy, the authors
of the Critical Naturalism Manifesto miss the opportunity to theorize how some forms
of capitalism and economic theories might actually become potential allies in the aus-
picated change.
References
Braidotti, Rosi. 2013. The Posthuman. Cambridge: Polity.
Brassier, Ray. 2013. “That Which is Not: Philosophy as Entwinement of Truth and Negativity.” Stasis 1 (1) 174-
186.
Broome, John. 2012. Climate Matters: Ethics in a Warming World. New York: WW Norton & Company.
Bruni, Luigino, and Stefano Zamagni. 2016. Civil Economy: Another Idea of the Market. Newcastle-Upon-Tyne:
Agenda Publishing.
Dasgupta, Partha. 2021. The Economics of Biodiversity: The Dasgupta Review. Hm Treasury.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. 1980. Mille plateaux. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.
Kant, Immanuel. 1929 [1787]. Critique of Pure Reason. London: MacMillan.
Latour, Bruno. 2017. Facing Gaia: Eight Lectures on the New Climatic Regime. Cambridge: Polity.
Mazzucato, Marianna. 2013. The Entrepreneurial State: Debunking Public vs. Private Sector Myths. Lon-
don: Anthem Press.
Mittiga, Ross. 2019. “What’s the Problem with Geo-Engineering?” Social Theory and Practice 45 (3), 47199.
Neurath, Otto. 1973 [1921]. “Anti-Spengler.” In Empiricism and Sociology, edited by Marie Neurath and Robert
Krisis 2023, 43 (1)
109
S. Cohen, 158-214. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1980. Sämtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe. Edited by G. Colli and M. Montinari.
Berlin: De Gruyter/ Munich: DTV.
Quine, W.V.O. 1969. “Epistemology Naturalized.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Co-
lumbia University Press.
Raworth, Kate. 2017. Doughnut Economics: Seven Ways to Think Like a 21st-Century Economist. Vermont:
Chelsea Green Publishing.
Regan, Tom. 1983. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Schaefer, G. Owen, and Julian Savulescu. 2014. “The Ethics of Producing in Vitro Meat.” Journal of Applied
Philosophy 31 (2): 188202.
Singer, Peter. 1977. Animal Liberation. New York: Avon Books.
Biography
Martine Prange is Full Professor of Humanity, Culture and Society. Her research focuses on the History of
Modernity, Continental Philosophy, contemporary questions of free speech, critique, and media as well of 'public
listening' and 'auditive democracy' (the philosophy and art of listening, attention, and silence). She also teaches
philosophical anthropology, posthumanism, and the Anthropocene.
Ties van Gemert is a PhD-student at the Department of Philosophy of Tilburg University. His research interests
are in epistemology, philosophy of science, and history of psychology.
Willem van der Deijl is assistant professor of ethics at the Tilburg Philosophy Department. His research is
focused on wellbeing, meaningfulness, and questions of value more generally.
Paolo Santori defines himself as a philosopher at the crossroads between economic thought and theology. Cur-
rently, he is Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy of the Tilburg School of Humanities and Digital
Sciences (Tilburg University). He obtained (2022) the Italian National Scientific Habilitation as Associate Pro-
fessor in History of Econonomic Thought.