2021, issue 2
Dwarf Fruit, or: The Impertinent Self
Josef Früchtl
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons
Attribution 4.0 License International License (CC
BY 4.0). © 2021 The author(s).
DOI Licence
Krisis 41 (2): 74-75.
10.21827/krisis.41.2.38246
742021, issue 2
Dwarf Fruit, or: The Impertinent Self
Josef Früchtl
One might think that dwarf fruit is fruit for human beings so small that in our imagi-
nation they tend to populate myths and fairy tales. But dwarf fruit is simply the name
for fruit that grows on little trees, even in a big pot on the balcony. It does not dier
from the fruit apples, pears, cherries, plums of bigger trees, but it ripens faster.
Thus, though the tree seems ridiculously small, the fruit the apple is as sappy and
sweet-sour as you like to have it. It may even give you a kick as if it were from the tree
of knowledge.
“Dwarf fruit” is also the title of an aphorism it is number 29 in Theodor
W. Adorno’s Minima Moralia that arranges a series of short sentences, among them the
famous and last one: “The whole is the false”, inverting Hegel’s: “The true is the whole”.
Another sentence has also become famous, or at least it has caused some trouble and
personal criticism. It sounds laconic, and at rst sight the implicit scandal may escape
the reader: “In many people it is already an impertinence to say ‘I’”.
In principle, saying ‘I’ is the simple, and at the same time crucial, characteristic of
that kind of being that is able to refer to itself and to identify itself in verbal language. It is
the privilege of articulated self-consciousness in the shape of human beings. But – here
we go again – Hegel has already told us that there is a specic contradiction or dialectic
in using the pronoun “I”. Whoever uses it refers to a Self that is absolutely individual
and at the same time thoroughly universal. By saying “I” we distinguish ourselves from
all other beings able to say “I”, and this includes expressing what is common to all of us,
namely the capacity to say “I” and thus express self-consciousness.
Given the historical conditions of the 1940s when Adorno wrote down his
Minima Moralia, the Self that proudly presents itself by saying ‘I’ is nothing but a univer-
sal cover that includes in fact nothing, at least nothing individual. The whole that has
become the false is the whole of a totalising systematic theory, the totalitarian state, the
“iron cage” of capitalism (Max Weber), and the ideological manipulation of the “culture
industry”. Saying “I” under such circumstances is the sad prerogative of a few critical
intellectuals, artists, and philosophers, but for the majority of people it is an imperti-
nence. They claim to be individuals, but in fact their individualism is fake. This can be
conrmed by a prominent line of theorists after Hegel, a line that connects Marx and
Kierkegaard (about whom Adorno wrote his rst philosophical book) with Nietzsche,
Freud and Weber. But following the aphoristically sharpened dialectical thinking of
Minima Moralia, it can also be conrmed in apparently small gestures and expressions.
For example, if we hear someone talking about a work of art - a Beethoven symphony
or a play by Beckett by simply saying: “I like it”, thus using a catch-all term to describe
a specic experience, we have to admit far from being impertinent ourselves - that we
are confronted with faked individualism (Adorno 1992, 244).
This is the story Adorno is telling us. Or more precisely, it is the main story.
For in between his rm and exaggerated statements there are dierentiations and
doubts. Above all in the 1960s, twenty years after having written Minima Moralia in his
US-American exile, Adorno becomes more and more aware of a split consciousness
752021, issue 2
in all these people who are shaped by the absorbing power of a capitalist consumer
society. Their individualism is not only fake. They show a tension between having fun
and doubting it, or the other way round: despising something intellectually while liking
it aectively. While a band playing traditional German music for brass instruments is
marching past and the young intellectual standing at the wayside contemptuously twists
his mouth, he realises that he is following the primitive beat by pounding softly with
his right foot.
Since the 1960s, for a larger proportion of the readers of Adorno, popular music
has been as important as the texts of the philosopher. They have learnt that they can
do one thing – listening to the music of Beethoven – while not abandoning another –
dancing to the music of Chuck Berry (and a lot of other rock ‘n’ roll bands). For them
there is no demand for Beethoven to “roll over”. There is the demand to make room
for rock ‘n’ roll, certainly, but not entirely, only to an equal extent. So, the revolting
students of the 1960s (and later) also know about the contradiction they themselves
incorporate. To express it simply with a refrain from the Rolling Stones: “I know it’s
only rock ‘n’ roll, but I like it”. I really know that it is only rock ‘n’ roll, but I like it
because it expresses what I – together with a lot of other people – feel. It is – expressed
in ne Hegelian language a form of cultural self-assurance or sensuous self-reection.
Adorno certainly is a burnt child and thus xated on the continuing elements of a
totalitarian society after World War II, but the re-educated children of the ruins start
dancing and ghting in the street while carrying Minima Moralia in their pockets and
digesting its bitter-sweet dwarf fruit.
References
Adorno, Theodor W. 1992. “An Open Letter to
Rolf Hochhuth. In Notes to Literature, Vol. Two,
transl. by Shierry Weber Nicholson. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Josef Früchtl is professor of philosophy with a focus
on philosophy of art and culture (Critical Cultural
Theory) at the University of Amsterdam (UvA).
He is publishing in the field of aesthetics (with a
focus on aesthetics and ethics as well as aesthetics
and politics), Critical Theory, theory of Modernity,
and philosophy of film. His recent publication is
Vertrauen in die Welt. Eine Philosophie des Films
(München: Fink 2013), translated as Trust in the
World. A Philosophy of Film (New York & London:
Routledge 2018).
Biography